One of Modern Library's 100 Best Nonfiction Books of the Twentieth Century
In
this classic study of how people learned to retain vast stores of
knowledge before the invention of the printed page, Frances A. Yates
traces the art of memory from its treatment by Greek orators, through
its Gothic transformations in the Middle Ages, to the occult forms it
took in the Renaissance, and finally to its use in the seventeenth
century. This book, the first to relate the art of memory to the history
of culture as a whole, was revolutionary when it first appeared and
continues to mesmerize readers with its lucid and revelatory insights.
The Art of Memory according to Ad Herennium
Frances
Yates
An unknown teacher of rhetoric in rome complied, circa 86-82 B.C., a useful text-book for his students which immortalised, not his own name, but the name of the man to whom it was dedicated. It is somewhat tiresome that this work, so vitally important for the history of the classical art of memory [...] has no other title save the uniformative Ad Herennium. The busy and efficient teacher goes through the five parts of rhetoric (inventio, dispositio, elocutio, memoria, pronuntiatio) in a rather dry text-book style. When he comes to memory as an essential part of the orator's equipment, he opens his treatment of it with the words: 'Now let us turn to the treasure-house of inventions, the custodian of all the parts of rhetoric, memory.' There are two kinds of memory [Ad Herennium claims], one natural, the other artificial. The natural memory is that which is engrafted in our minds, born simultaneously with thought. The artificial memory is a memory strengthened or confirmed by training. A good natural memory can be improved by this discipline and persons less well endowed can have their weak memories improved by the art.
After this curt preamble the author announces abruptly, 'Now we will speak of the artificial memory.'
An immense
weight of history presses on the memory section of Ad Herennium.
It is drawing on Greek sources of memory teaching, probably in Greek treatises
on rhetoric all of which are lost. It is the only Latin treatise on the
subject to be preserved, for Cicero's and Quintilian's remarks are not
full treatises and assume that the reader is already familiar with the
artificial memory and its terminology. It is thus really the main source,
and indeed the only complete source, for the classical art of memory both
in the Greek and in the Latin world. Its rôle as the transmitter
of the classical art to the Middle Ages and the Renaissance is also of
unique importance. The Ad Herennium was a well known and much used
text in the Middle Ages when it had an immense prestige because it was
thought to be by Cicero. It was therefore believed that the precepts for
the artificial memory which it expounded had been drawn up by 'Tullius'
himself.
In short,
all attempts to puzzle out what the classical art of memory was like must
be mainly based on the memory section of Ad Herennium. And all
attempts such as we are making in this book to puzzle out the history
of that art in the Western tradition must refer back constantly to this
text as the main source of the tradition. Every Ars memorativa
treatise, with its rules for 'places', its rules for 'images', its discussion
of 'memory for things' and 'memory for words', is repeating the plan,
the subject matter, and as often as not the actual words of Ad Herennium.
And the astonishing developments of the art of memory in the sixteenth
century [...] still preserve the 'Ad Herennian' outlines below all their
complex accretions. Even the wildest flights of fancy in such a work as
Giordano Bruno's I cannot conceal the fact that the philosopher of the
Renaissance is going through yet once again the old, old business of rules
for places, rules for images, memory for things, memory for words.
Evidently,
therefore, it is incumbent upon us to attempt the by no means easy task
of trying to understand the memory section of Ad Herennium. What
makes the task by no means easy is that the rhetoric teacher is not addressing
us; he is not setting out to explain to people who know nothing about
it what the artificial memory was. He is addressing his rhetoric students
as they congregated around him circa 86-82 B.C., and they
knew what he was talking about; for them he needed only to rattle
off the 'rules' which they would know how to apply. We are in a different
case and are often somewhat baffled by the strangeness of some of the
memory rules.
In what follows I attempt to give the content of the memory section of
Ad Herennium, emulating the brisk style of the author, but with
pauses for reflection about what he is telling us.
The artificial
memory is established from places and images (Constat igitur artificiosa
memoria ex locis et imaginibus), the definition to be forever repeated
down the ages. A locus is a place easily grasped by the memory,
such as a house, an intercolumnar space, a corner, an arch, or the like.
Images are forms, marks or simulacra (formae, notae, simulacra)
of what we wish to remember. For instance if we wish to recall the genus
of a horse, of a lion, of an eagle, we must place their images on definite
loci.
The art of
memory is like an inner writing. Those who know the letters of the alphabet
can write down what is dictated to them and read out what they have written.
Likewise those who have learned mnemonics can set in places what they
have heard and deliver it from memory. 'For the
places are very much like wax tablets or papyrus, the images like the
letters, the arrangement and disposition of the images like the script,
and the delivery is like the reading.'
If we wish
to remember much material we must equip ourselves with a large number
of places. It is essential that the places should form a series and must
be remembered in their order, so that we can start from any locus
in the series and move either backwards or forwards from it. If we should
see a number of our acquaintances standing in a row, it would not make
any difference to us whether we should tell their names beginning with
the person standing at the head of the line or at the foot or in the middle.
So with memory loci. 'If these have been
arranged in order, the result will be that, reminded by the images, we
can repeat orally what we have committed to the loci, proceeding
in either direction from any locus we please.'
The formation
of the loci is of the greatest importance, for the same set of
loci can be used again and again for remembering different material.
The images which we have placed on them for remembering one set of things
fade and are effaced when we make no further use of them. But the loci
remain in the memory and can be used again by placing another set
of images for another set of material. The loci are like the wax
tablets which remain when what is written on them has been effaced and
are ready to be written on again.
In order
to make sure that we do not err in remembering the order of the loci
it is useful to give each fifth locus some distinguishing mark.
We may for example mark the fifth locus with a golden hand, and
place in the tenth the image of some acquaintance whose name is Decimus.
We can then go on to station other marks on each succeeding fifth locus.
It is better
to form one's memory loci in a deserted and solitary place for
crowds of passing people tend to weaken the impressions. Therefore the
student intent on acquiring a sharp and well-defined set of loci
will choose an unfrequented building in which to memorise places.
Memory loci
should not be too much like one another, for instance too many intercolumnar
spaces are not good, for their resemblance to one another will be confusing.
They should be of moderate size, not too large for this renders the images
placed on them vague, and not too small for then an arrangement of images
will be overcrowded. They must not be too brightly lighted for then the
images placed on them will glitter and dazzle; nor must they be too dark
or the shadows will obscure the images. The intervals between the loci
should be of moderate extent, perhaps about thirty feet, 'for
like the external eye, so the inner eye of thought is less powerful when
you have moved the object of sight too near or too far away'.
A person
with a relatively large experience can easily equip himself with as many
suitable loci as he pleases, and even a person who thinks that
he does not possess enough sufficiently good loci can remedy this.
'For thought can embrace any region whatsoever and
in it and at will construct the setting of some locus.' (That is
to say, mnemonics can use what were afterwards called 'fictitious places',
in contrast to the 'real places' of the ordinary method.)
Pausing for
reflection at the end of rules for places I would say that what strikes
me most about them is the astonishing visual precision which they imply.
In a classically trained memory the space between the loci can
be measured, the lighting of the loci is allowed for. And the rules
summon up a vision of a forgotten social habit. Who is that man moving
slowly in the lonely building, stopping at intervals with an intent face
? He is a rhetoric student fomiing a set of memory loci.
'Enough
has been said of places', continues the author of Ad Herennium,
'now we turn to the theory of images.' Rules
for images now begin, the first of which is that there are two kinds of
images, one for 'things' (res), the other for 'words' (verba).
That is to say 'memory for things' makes images to remind of an argument,
a notion, or a 'thing'; but 'memory for words' has to find images to remind
of every single word.
I interrrupt the concise author here for a moment in order to remind the reader that for the rhetoric student 'things' and 'words' would have an absolutely precise meaning in relation to the five parts of the rhetoric. Those five parts are defined by Cicero as follows:
Invention is the excogitation of true things (res), or things similar to truth to render one's cause plausible; disposition is the arrangement in order of the things thus discovered; elocution is the accomodation of suitable words to the invented (things); memory is the firm perception in the soul of things and words; pronunciation is the moderating of the voice and body to suit the dignity of the things and words. [De inventione, I, vii, 9]
'Things'
are thus the subject matter of the speech; 'words' are the language in
which that subject matter is clothed. Are you aiming at an artificial
memory to remind you only of the order of the notions, arguments, 'things'
of your speech ? Or do you aim at memorising every single word in it in
the right order ? The first kind of artificial memory is memoria rerum;
the second kind is memoria verborum. The ideal, as defined by Cicero
in the above passage, would be to have a 'firm perception
in the soul' of both things and words. But 'memory for words' is
much harder than 'memory for things'; the weaker brethren among the author
of Ad Herennium's rhetoric students evidently rather jibbed at
memorising an image for every single word, and even Cicero himself, as
we shall see later, allowed that 'memory for things' was enough.
To return to the rules for images. We have already been given the rules for places, what kind of places to choose for memorising. What are the rules about what kind of images to choose for memorising on the places? We now come to one of the most curious and surprising passages in the treatise, namely the psychological reasons which the author gives for the choice of mnemonic images. Why is it, he asks, that some images are so strong and sharp and so suitable for awakening memory, whilst others are so weak and feeble that they hardly stimulate memory at all? We must enquire into this so as to know which images to avoid and which to seek.
Now nature herself teaches us what we should do. When we see in every day life things that are petty, ordinary, and banal, we generally fail to remember them, because the mind is not being stirred by anything novel or marvellous. But if we see or hear something exceptionally base, dishonourable, unusual, great, unbelievable, or ridiculous, that we are likely to remember for a long time. Accordingly, things immediate to our eye or ear we commonly forget; incidents of our childhood we often remember best. Nor could this be so for any other reason than that ordinary things easily slip from the memory while the striking and the novel stay longer in the mind. A sunrise, the sun's course, a sunset are marvellous to no one because they occur daily. But solar eclipses are a source of wonder because they occur seldom, and indeed are more marvellous than lunar eclipses, because these are more frequent. Thus nature shows that she is not aroused by the common ordinary event, but is moved by a new or striking occurrence. Let art, then, imitate nature, find what she desires, and follow as she directs. For in invention nature is never last, education never first; rather the beginnings of things arise from natural talent, and the ends are reached by discipline.
We ought, then, to set up images of a kind that can adhere longest in memory. And we shall do so if we establish similitudes as striking as possible; if we set up images that are not many or vague but active (imagines agentes); if we assign to them exceptional beauty or singular ugliness; if we ornament some of them, as with crowns or purple cloaks, so that the similitude may be more distinct to us; or if we somehow disfigure them, as by introducing one stained with blood or soiled with mud or smeared with red paint, so that its form is more striking, or by assigning certain comic effects to our images, for that, too, will ensure our remembering them more readily. The things we easily remember when they are real we likewise remember without difficulty when they are figments. But this will be essential - again and again to run over rapidly in the mind all the original places in order to refresh the images. [Ad Herennium, III, xxii]
Our author
has clearly got hold of the idea of helping memory by arousing emotional
affects through these striking and unusual images, beautiful or hideous,
comic or obscene. And it is clear that he is thinking of human images,
of human figures wearing crowns or purple cloaks, bloodstained or smeared
with paint, of human figures dramatically engaged in some activity - doing
something. We feel that we have moved into an extraordinary world as we
run over his places with the rhetoric student, imagining on the places
such very peculiar images. Quintilian's anchor
and weapon as memory images, though much less exciting, are easier
to understand than the weirdly populated memory to which the author of
Ad Herennium introduces us.
It is one
of the many difficulties which confront the student of the history of
the art of memory that an Ars memorativa treatise though it will
always give the rules, rarely gives any concrete application of the rules,
that is to say it rarely sets out a system of mnemonic images on their
places. This tradition was started by the author of Ad Hennnium
himself who says that the duty of an instructor in mnemonics is to teach
the method of making images, give a few examples, and then encourage the
student to form his own. When teaching 'introductions', he says, one does
not draft a thousand set introductions and give them to the student to
learn by heart; one teaches him the method and then leaves him to his
own inventiveness. So also one should do in teaching mnemonic images.
This is an admirable tutorial principle though one regrets that it prevents
the author from showing us a whole set or gallery of striking and unusual
imagines agentes. We must be content with the three specimens which
he describes.
The first is an example of a 'memory for things' image. We have to suppose that we are the counsel for the defence in a law suit. 'The prosecutor has said that the defendant killed a man by poison, has charged that the motive of the crime was to gain an inheritance, and declared that there are many witnesses and accessories to this act.' We are forming a memory system about the whole case and we shall wish to put in our first memory locus an image to remind us of the accusation against our client. This is the image.
We shall imagine the man in question as lying illin bed, if we know him personally. If we do not know him, we shall yet take some one to be our invalid, but not a man of the lowest class, so that he may come to mind at once. And we shall place the defendant at the bedside, holding in his right hand a cup, in his left, tablets, and on the fourth finger, a ram's testicles. In this way we can have in memory the man who was poisoned, the witnesses, and the inheritance.
The cup would
remind of the poisoning, the tablets, of the will or the inheritance,
and the testicles of the ram through verbal similarity with testes
- of the witnesses. The sick man is to be like the man himself, or like
someone else whom we know (though not one of the anonymous lower classes).
In the following loci we would put other counts in the charge,
or the details of the rest of the case, and if we have properly imprinted
the places and images we shall easily be able to remember any point that
we wish to recall.
This, then,
is an example of a classical memory image - consisting of human figures,
active, dramatic, striking, with accessories to remind of the whole 'thing'
which is being recorded in memory. Though everything appears to be explained,
I yet find this image baffling. Like much else in Ad Herennium
on memory it seems to belong to a world which is either impossible for
us to understand or which is not being really fully explained to us.
The writer
is not concerned in this example with remembering the speeches in the
case but with recording the details or 'things' of the case. It is as
though, as a lawyer, he is forming a filing cabinet in memory of his cases.
The image given is put as a label on the first place of the memory file
on which the records about the man accused of poisoning are kept. He wants
to look up something about that case; he turns to the composite image
in which it is recorded, and behind that image on the following places
he finds the rest of the case. If this is at all a correct interpretation,
the artificial memory would now be being used, not only to memorise speeches,
but to hold in memory a mass of material which can be looked up at will.
The words
of Cicero in the De oratore when he is speaking of the advantages
of the artificial memory may tend to confirm this interpretation. He has
just been saying that the loci preserve the order of the facts,
and the images designate the facts themselves, and we employ the places
and images like a wax writing tablet and the letters written on it. 'But
what business is it of mine', he continues, 'to
specify the value to a speaker and the usefulness and effectiveness of
memory? of retaining the information given you when you were briefed and
the opinions you yourself have formed? of having all your ideas firmly
planted in your mind and all your resources of vocabulary neatly arranged,
of giving such close attention to the instructions of your client and
to the speech of the opponent you have to answer that they may seem not
just to pour what they say into your ears but to imprint it on your mind?
Consequently only people with a powerful memory know what they are going
to say and for how long they are going to speak and in what style, what
points they have already answered and what still remains; and they can
also remember from other cases many arguments which they have previously
advanced and many which they have heard from other people.'
We are in
the presence of amazing powers of memory. And, according to Cicero, these
natural powers were indeed aided by training of the type described in
Ad Herennium.
The specimen
image just described was a 'memory for things' image; it was designed
to recall the 'things' or facts of the case and the following loci
of the system would presumably have held other 'memory for things' images,
recording other facts about the case or arguments used in speeches by
the defence or the prosecution. The other two specimen images given in
Ad Herennium are 'memory for words' images.
The student
wishing to acquire 'memory for words' begins in the same way as the 'memory
for things' student; that is to say he memorises places which are to hold
his images. But he is confronted with a harder task for far more places
will be needed to memorise all the words of a speech than would be needed
for its notions. The specimen images for 'memory for words' are of the
same type as the 'memory for things' image, that is to say they represent
human figures of a striking and unusual character and in striking dramatic
situations - imagines agentes.
We are setting out to memorise this line of verse:
Iam domum itionem reges Atridae parant
(And now their homecoming the kings, the sons of Atreus are making ready)
The line
is found only in the quotation of it in Ad Herennium and was either
invented by the author to exhibit his mnemonic technique or was taken
for some lost work. It is to be memorised through two very extraordinary
images.
One is 'Domitius
raising his hands to heaven while he is lashed by the Marcii Reges'.
The translator and editor of the text in the Loeb edition (H. Caplan)
explains in a note that 'Rex was the name of one of the most distinguished
families of the Marcian gens; the Domitian, of plebeian origin, was likewise
a celebrated gens'. The image may reflect some street scene in which Domitius
of the plebeian gens (perhaps bloodstained to make him more memorable)
is being beaten up by some members of the distinguished Rex family. It
was perhaps a scene which the author himself had witnessed. Or perhaps
it was a scene in some play. It was a striking scene in every sense of
the word and therefore suitable as a mnemonic image. It was put on a place
for remembering this line. The vivid image immediately brought to mind
'Domitius-Reges' and this reminded by sound
resemblance of 'domum itionem reges'. It
thus exhibits the principles of a 'memory for words' image which brings
to mind the words which the memory is seeking through their sound resemblance
to the notion suggested by the image.
We all know
how, when groping in memory for a word or a name, some quite absurd and
random association, something which has 'stuck' in the memory, will help
us to dredge it up. The classical art is systematising that process.
The other
image for memorising the rest of the line is 'Aesopus
and Cimber being dressed for the roles of Agamemnon and Menelaus in Iphigenaia'.
Aesopus was a well-known tragic actor, a friend of Cicero; Cimber, evidently
also an actor, is only mentioned in this text. The play in which they
are preparing to act also does not exist. In the image these actors are
being dressed to play the parts of the sons of Atreus (Agamemnon and Menelaus).
It is an exciting off-stage glimpse of two famous actors being made up
(to smear an image with red paint makes it memorable according to the
rules) and dressed for their parts. Such a scene has an the elements of
a good mnemonic image; we therefore use it to remember 'Atridae
parant', the sons of Atreus are making ready. This image immediately
gave the word 'Atridae' (though not by sound
resemblance) and also suggested 'making ready' for the home-coming through
the actors making ready for the
stage.
This method
for memorising the verse will not work by itself, says the author of Ad
Herennium. We must go over the verse three or four times, that is
learn it by heart in the usual way, and then represent the words by means
of images. 'In this way art will supplement nature.
For neither by itself will be strong enough, though we must note that
theory and technique are much the more rehable.' The fact that
we have to learn the poem by heart as well, makes 'memory for words' a
little less baffling.
Reflecting
on the 'memory for words' images, we note that our author seems now concerned
not with the rhetoric students' proper business of remembering a speech,
but with memorising verse in poems or plays. To remember a whole poem
or a whole play in this way one has to envisage 'places' extending one
might almost say for miles within the memory, 'places' past which one
moves in reciting, drawing from them the mnemonic cues. And perhaps that
word 'cue' does give a clue to how the method might be workable. Did one
really learn the poem by heart but set up some places with 'cue' images
on them at strategic intervals ?
Our author
mentions that another type of 'memory for words' symbol has been elaborated
by the Greeks. 'I know that most of the Greeks who
have written on the memory have taken the course of listing images that
correspond to a great many words, so that persons who wished to learn
these images by heart would have them ready without expending effort in
a search for them.' It is possible that these Greek images for
words are shorthand symbols or notae the use of which was coming
into fashion in the Latin world at this time. As used in mnemonics, this
would presumably mean that, by a kind of inner stenography, the shorthand
symbols were written down inwardly and memorised on the memory places.
Fortunately our author disapproves of this method, since even a thousand
of such ready-made symbols would not begin to cover all the words used.
Indeed, he is rather lenient about 'memory for words' of any kind; it
must be tackled just because it is more difficult than 'memory for things'.
It is to be used as an exercise to strengthen 'that
other kind of memory, the memory for things, which is of practical use.
Thus we may without effort pass from this difficult training to ease in
that other memory.'
The memory
section closes with an exhortation to hard work. 'In
every discipline artistic theory is of little avail without unremitting
exercise, but especially in mnemonics, theory is almost valueless unless
made good by industry, devotion, toil, and care. You can make sure that
you have as many places as possible and that these conform as much as
possible to the rules; in placing the images you should exercise every
day.'
We have been
trying to understand inner gymnastics, invisible labours of concentration
which are to us most strange, though the rules and examples of Ad Herennium
give mysterious glimpses into the powers and organisation of antique memories.
We think of memory feats which are recorded of the ancients, of how the
elder Seneca, a teacher of rhetoric, could repeat two thousand names in
the order in which they had been given; and when a class of two hundred
students or more spoke each in turn a line of poetry, he could recite
all the lines in reverse order, beginning from the last one said and going
right back to the first. Or we remember that Augustine, also trained as
a teacher of rhetoric, tells of a friend called Simplicius who could recite
Virgil backwards. We have learned from our text-book that if we have properly
and firmly fixed our memory places we can move along them in either direction,
backwards or forwards. The artificial memory may explain the awe inspiring
ability to recite backwards of the elder Seneca and of Augustine's friend.
Pointless though such feats may seem to us, they illustrate the respect
accorded in antiquity to the man with the trained memory.
Very singular is the art of this invisible art of memory. It reflects ancient architecture but in an unclassical spirit, concentrating its choice on irregular places and avoiding symmetrical orders. It is full of human imagery of a very personal kind; we mark the tenth place with a face like that of our friend Decimus; we see a number of our acquaintances standing in a row; we visualise a sick man like the man himself, or if we did not know him, like someone we do know. These human figures are active and dramatic, strikingly beautiful or grotesque. They remind one more of figures in some Gothic cathedral than of classical art proper. They appear to be completely amoral, their function being solely to give an emotional impetus to memory by their personal idiosyncracy or their strangeness. This impression may, however, be due to the fact that we have not been given a specimen image of how to remember, for example, the 'things' justice or temperance and their parts, which are treated by the author of Ad Herennium when discussing the invention of the subject matter of a speech. The elusiveness of the art of memory is very trying to its historian.
'Books > nonfiction' 카테고리의 다른 글
A Preface to Morals (0) | 2017.05.24 |
---|---|
Religion and the rise of capitalism (0) | 2017.05.24 |
THE OPEN SOCIETY AND ITS ENEMIES (0) | 2017.05.24 |
The Second World War (0) | 2017.05.24 |
Working (0) | 2017.05.24 |